Mar 8, 2011

Elegi Menggapai "KANT’S AESTHETICS JUDGMENT"



By Marsigit


In the Critique of Judgment , Kant, 1790, outlined the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment consists of Analytic of Aesthetic Judgment and Dialectic of Aesthetic Judgment in which to be elaborated also the Analytic of Beautiful includes the kinds of the judgment of taste; and Analytic of Sublime includes the mathematically the sublime and the dynamically sublime in the nature.



It was stated in Burnham, 2003, that the predicate “aesthetic” can qualify many different kinds of things: judgments, experiences, concepts, properties, or words.

We can understand other aesthetic kinds of things in terms of aesthetic judgments: aesthetic properties are those that are ascribed in aesthetic judgments; aesthetic experiences are those that ground aesthetic judgments; aesthetic concepts are those that are deployed in aesthetic judgments; and aesthetic words are those that are typically used in the linguistic expression of aesthetic judgments.

The document noted that the basic explicit purpose of Kant's Critique of Judgment is to investigate whether the faculty of judgment provides itself with an a priori principle.

Kant assumed that judgment was simply a name for the combined operation of other mental faculties and speculated that the operation of judgment might be organized and directed by a fundamental a priori principle that is unique to it.

Kant insisted that the faculty of understanding is that which supplies concepts that is universals, and reason is that which draws inferences e.g. constructs syllogisms, and judgment 'mediates' between the understanding and reason by allowing individual acts of sub-sumption to occur; he then distinguished between determinate and reflective judgments.

Aesthetic judgments, according to Kant, to be a particularly interesting form of reflective judgments.


The Judgment of the Beautiful


Burnham, 2003, noted Kant that an aesthetic judgments or judgments of taste must have four key distinguishing features: disinterested, universal, necessary and final without end.

It is disinterested because it is pleasurable judgment; it is universal and necessity because it is in fact a product of features of the human mind; and it is purposive without purpose or final without end because it is the concept according to which it was made that an object is purposive if it appears to have such a purpose, or in other word they should affect us as if they had a purpose, although no particular purpose can be found.

Having identified the major features of aesthetic judgments, Kant then delivered the questions how such judgments are possible, and are such
judgments in any way valid that is, are they really universal and necessary.

Kant initially focused on judgments about beauty in nature to answer what does such a judgment mean, and how does it take place as a mental act; he then needs to clarify the basic features of such judgments and concluded that on aesthetic judgments there must have a number of peculiar features which at first sight look like nothing other than paradoxes that he called 'moments'; the first moment is “disinterested”, the second moment is “universal”, the third moment is “purposiveness” , and the fourth moment is “necessary”.

Kant outlined that there are two types of interest that are by way of sensations in the agreeable, and by way of concepts in the good; only aesthetic judgment is free or pure of any such interests.

He defined interest as a link to real desire and action, and thus also to a determining connection to the real existence of the object.

According to Kant, in the aesthetic judgment, the real existence of the beautiful object is quite irrelevant and that aesthetic judgments are disinterested .

He claimed that judgment results in pleasure, rather than pleasure resulting in judgment; and the aesthetic judgment must concern itself only with form in the object presented, not sensible content.

Burnham, 2003, elaborated. Kant’s claims that aesthetic judgments behave universally; if we judge a certain landscape to be beautiful, we at least implicitly demand universality in the name of taste.

Kant argues that there is always a tendency to see 'beauty' as if it were somehow in the object or the immediate experience of the object and that such a relativist view can not account for the social behavior of our claims about what we find beautiful.

Meanwhile, Kant claimed that an object's purpose is the concept according to which it was manufactured; therefore, purposiveness is the property of at least appearing to have been manufactured or designed.

Kant concluded that the beautiful has to be understood as purposive, but without any definite purpose because a definite purpose would be either the set of external purposes or the internal purpose.

Accordingly, beauty is equivalent neither to utility nor perfection, but is still purposive; in nature, it will appear as purposive with respect to our faculty of judgment, but its beauty will have no ascertainable purpose that is, it is not purposive with respect to determinate cognition.

Burnham, 2003, also elaborated Kant’s claims that aesthetic judgments must pass the test of being necessary that the judgment does not either follow or produce a determining concept of beauty, but exhausts itself in being exemplary precisely of an aesthetic judgment.


The Deduction of Taste


Burnham, 2003, noted Kant that our faculty or ability to judge consisted of being a mere processor of other, much more fundamental mental presentations that are concepts and intuitions; everything interesting and fundamental happened in the formation of concepts, or in the receiving of intuitions.

However, Kant argued that judgment has a fundamental principle that governs it that asserts the purposiveness of all phenomena with respect to our judgment or everything we experience can be tackled by our powers of judgment.

Kant claimed that in the case of the beautiful we do notice that this assumption is being made because the beautiful not only draws particular attention to its purposiveness but also has no concept of a purpose available, so that we cannot just apply a concept and be
done with it; the beautiful forces us to grope for concepts that we can never find and it is not an alien and disturbing experience, on the contrary, it is pleasurable; the principle of purposiveness is satisfied, but in a new and unique way.

According to Kant, as noted by Burnham, 2003, that the kinds of cognition characteristic of the contemplation of the beautiful are not all that different from ordinary cognition about things in the world; the faculties of the mind are 'understanding' which is responsible for concepts, and 'sensibility' which is responsible for intuitions.

Kant argued in aesthetic cognition there is no one determinate concept that pins down an intuition; intuition is allowed some free play and acts in harmony with the lawfulness in general of the understanding as common sense; hence the common sense was plausible as a possible explanation of the tendency to universality observed in aesthetic judgments.

Throughout the Four Moments of the Beautiful, Kant elaborated many important clues as to the transcendental account of the possibility of aesthetic judgment e.g. communicability, common sense and the harmony of the cognitive sub-faculties.

By deduction Kant explicitly attempted to demonstrate the universal communicability and thus inter-subjective validity of judgments of taste that there is a 'common sense' that humans all must have a kind of sensing ability which operates the same way.


The Sublime


For Kant, as it elaborated by Burnham, 2003, the other basic type of aesthetic experience is the sublime that is idea of absolute totality or absolute freedom, and thus the sublime is a kind of rapid alternation between the fear of the overwhelming and the peculiar pleasure of seeing that overwhelming overwhelmed.

According to Kant, the connection between the sublime and morality can be raised up that the whole sublime experience would not be possible if humans had not received a moral training that taught them to recognize the importance of their own faculty of reason.

Kant noted that while the beautiful is concerned with form, the sublime may even be formless and while the beautiful indicates a purposiveness of nature that may have profound implications, the sublime appears to be counter-purposive, as well as although from the above one might expect the sublime experience to be painful in some way, in fact the sublime does still involve pleasure.

Kant, as it elaborated by Burnham, 2003, divides the sublime into the 'mathematical' that is concerned with things that have a great magnitude in and of themselves and the 'dynamically' that is things that have a magnitude of force in relation to us, particularly our will.

He defined mathematical sublime as something absolutely large that is large beyond all comparison; objects of sense are called 'sublime' only by a kind of covert sleight-of-hand.

According to Kant, the sublime experience has two-layer process that are a contra-purposive layer in which our faculties of sense fail to complete their task of presentation, and a strangely purposive layer in which this very failure constitutes a 'negative exhibition' of the ideas of reason which could not otherwise be presented.

Kant insisted that in the dynamically sublime a 'might' or power is observed in nature that is irresistible with respect to our bodily or sensible selves; in particular, nature is called 'sublime merely because it elevates the imagination to the exhibition of those cases wherein the mind can be made to feel the sublimity that is proper to its vocation.

Kant suggested, as noted by Burnham,2003, that the sublimity belongs to human freedom which is unassailable to the forces of nature; such a conception of freedom as being outside the order of nature, but demanding action upon that order.

Fine Art and Genius

Kant, as noted by Burnham, 2003, argued that art can be tasteful and yet be soulless that certain something would make it more than just an artificial version of a beautiful natural object and what provides soul in fine art is an aesthetic idea that is a counterpart to a rational idea that is a concept that could never adequately be exhibited sensibly.

According to Kant, an aesthetic idea is as successful an attempt as possible to 'exhibit' the rational idea that is the talent of genius to generate aesthetic ideas, but that is not all; the mode of expression must be tasteful because the understanding's 'lawfulness' is the condition of the expression being in any sense universal and capable of being shared and the genius must find a mode of expression which allows a viewer not just to 'understand' the work conceptually but also to reach something like the same excited yet harmonious state of mind that the genius had in creating.

Kant begins by giving a long clarification of art.

As a general term, again, art refers to the activity of making according to a preceding notion.

If I make a chair, I must know, in advance, what a chair is.

We distinguish art from nature because (though we may judge nature purposive) we know in fact there is no prior notion behind the activity of a flower opening.

The flower doesn't have an idea of opening prior to opening - the flower doesn't have a mind or a will to have or execute ideas with.

Kant subdivided arts into mechanical and aesthetic; the former are those which never-the-less are controlled by some definite concept of a purpose to be produced and the latter are those wherein the immediate object is merely pleasure itself; and therefore, Kant distinguished between agreeable and fine art, the former produces pleasure through sensation alone and the latter through various types of cognitions.

Accordingly, fine art is a type of purposeful production and its production according to a concept of an object but it has no concept adequate to its production; else any judgment on it will fail one of the key features of all aesthetic judgments: namely purposiveness without a purpose and fine art therefore must both be, and not be, an art in general (Burnham, 2003).

Kant, as noted by Burnham, 2003, defined genius as the talent that gives the rule to art that is the innate mental predisposition through which nature gives the rule to art; therefore, talent is an innate productive ability of the artist and as such belongs itself to nature.

Kant noted that fine art is produced by individual humans, but not as contingent individuals that is not by human nature in the empirically known sense; and fine art as aesthetic can have no definite rules or concepts for producing or judging it as well as that the rule supplied by genius is more a rule governing what to produce, rather than how.

Kant then concluded that while all fine art is a beautiful 'presentation' of an object, this partly obscures the fact that genius is involved in the original creation of the object to be presented; genius provides the matter for fine art while taste provides the form and the beautiful is always formal.

He insisted that the aesthetic idea is a presentation of the imagination to which no thought is adequate and this is a 'counterpart' to rational ideas which are thoughts to which nothing sensible or imagined can be adequate.

Kant concluded that the cognition involved in judging fine art is similar to the cognition involved in judging natural beauty.

References:
1.Theodore Gracyk, © 2002, 2004 PHILOSOPHY OF ART, HUME AND KANT: Summary and Comparison, http://www.mnstate.edu/gracyk/courses/phil of art/ hume_and_kant.htm#6, elaborated that although some passages in the Critique of Judgment sound like a response to Hume, this is due to their common influences within the British tradition that regards the apprehension of beauty as an exercise of taste. With the Critique of Judgment, Kant's mature theory reveals a rethinking of art and taste as aspects of larger issues. Unfortunately, Kant then deals with them in relation to a complex, jargon-filled philosophical system. Burnham, 2003, Aesthetic Judgment of Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,http://plato.stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=aesthetic-judgment, noted that Kant's Critique of Judgment (the third Critique) was and continues to be a surprise - even to Kant, for it emerged out of Kant's philosophical activity having not been a part of the original plan. Thus, the central problem of the Critique of Judgment is a broad one: the unity of philosophy in general; his problem is investigated by that mental faculty which Kant believes is the key to this unity, namely judgment; nd judgment is investigated by the critical inquiry into those types of judgment in which the a priori principle of judgment is apparent: on the beautiful, on the sublime, and on teleology
2.Andrew Chignell, 2004, Aesthetics and Philosophy of the Arts: The Problem of Particularity in Kant’s Aesthetic Theory, andrew.chignell@yale.edu, indicated that an aesthetic judgment is unique in kind and provides absolutely no cognition (not even a confused one) of the object; only a logical judgment does that. An aesthetic judgment instead refers the presentation, by which an object is given, solely to the subject; it brings to our notice no characteristic of the object, but only the purposive form in the [way] the presentational powers are determined in their engagement with the object. Indeed, the judgment is called aesthetic precisely because the basis determining it is not a concept but the feeling (of the inner sense) of that accordance in the play of the mental powers insofar as it can only be sensed.
3.Theodore Gracyk, © 2002, 2004 PHILOSOPHY OF ART, HUME AND KANT: Summary and Comparison, http://www.mnstate.edu/gracyk/courses/phil of art/ hume_and_kant.htm#6, noted from Kant that human cognition also requires reflective judgment, in which our thinking is not determined by concepts already known. Kant proposes that taste comes into play in such situations, as a form of reflective judgment. In pure judgments of taste, Kant holds that the reflective judgment involves no recognition of the object as subsumed under a concept.
4.Andrew Chignell, 2004, Aesthetics and Philosophy of the Arts:The Problem of Particularity in Kant’s Aesthetic Theory, Yale University, andrew.chignell@yale.edu indicated that for Kant, the form of the aesthetic experience—the way our faculties interact upon being presented with beautiful objects—is the sine qua non of a well-formed judgment of taste; Savile violates the spirit of Kant’s theory when he has us attributing beauty to art objects because their conceptual content strikes us as expressive of rational ideas, and therefore as morally valuable. Of course, it is possible in principle for the imagination to call to mind associations of this sort for any presentation of sense; however, Kant seems to think that such an attempt with respect to a non-beautiful presentation will not produce pleasure. The non-beautiful object "leaves nothing behind as an [I]dea and makes the spirit dull, the object gradually disgusting, and the mind dissatisfied with itself and moody because it is conscious that in reason’s judgment its attunement is contrapurposive." Only an object that is connected "closely or remotely with moral ideas" will prove rich enough upon contemplation to avoid this "ultimate fate."
5.It was elaborated in Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc. Copyright © 1994-2000, that Kant’s work of the Critique of Judgment falls into two main parts, called respectively "Critique of Aesthetic Judgment" and "Critique of Teleological Judgment." In the first of these, after an introduction in which he discussed "logical purposiveness," he analyzed the notion of "aesthetic purposiveness" in judgments that ascribe beauty to something. Such a judgment, according to him, unlike a mere expression of taste, lays claim to general validity; yet it cannot be said to be cognitive because it rests on feeling, not on argument.
6.Nick Zangwill , 2003, Aesthetic Judgment Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy, nick.zangwill@st-catherines.oxford.ac.uk explained that, unlike other sorts of intentional pleasures, pleasure in beauty is “disinterested”. This means, very roughly, that it is a pleasure which does not involve desire -- pleasure in beauty is desire-free. That is, the pleasure is neither based on desire nor does it produce one by itself. In this respect, pleasure in beauty is unlike pleasure in the agreeable, unlike pleasure in what is good for me, and unlike pleasure in what is morally good. According to Kant, all such pleasures are “interested” -- they are bound up with desire.
7.Theodore Gracyk, © 2002, 2004 PHILOSOPHY OF ART, HUME AND KANT: Summary and Comparison, http://www.mnstate.edu/gracyk/courses/phil of art/ hume_and_kant.htm#6, noted that Hume and Kant try to escape this difficulty by denying that taste is a single, distinct faculty; they treat it as a complex response that involves sense perception, imagination, and judgment. Both writers ultimately use taste and art as a basis for investigating a much broader range of issues concerning human intersubjectivity.
8.Burnham, 2003, Aesthetic Judgment of Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato. stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=aesthetic-judgment, noted that throughout the Four Moments of the Beautiful, Kant has dropped many important clues as to the transcendental account of the possibility of aesthetic judgment: in particular, we have talked about communicability, common sense and the harmony of the cognitive sub-faculties. Kant then cuts off to turn to the sublime, representing a different problem within aesthetic judgment. He returns to beauty in sect.30, which forms the transition to the passages tantalizingly called the Deduction. These transitional passages feel much like a continuation of the Four Moments; we will treat them as such here, since also Kant claims that the sublime does not need a Deduction. The Deduction in fact appears in two versions in Kant's texts (sect.9 and 21 being the first; sect.30-40 the second, with further important clarification in the 'Dialectic' sect.55-58).
9.Ibid. Noted from Kant that of common sense, we explicitly are attempting to demonstrate the universal communicability and thus intersubjective validity of judgments of taste.
10.Burnham, 2003, Aesthetic Judgment of Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato. stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=aesthetic-judgment, noted that Traditionally, the sublime has been the name for objects inspiring awe, because of the magnitude of their size/height/depth (e.g. the ocean, the pyramids of Cheops), force (a storm), or transcendence (our idea of God). Vis-à-vis the beautiful, the sublime presents some unique puzzles to Kant. Three in particular are of note. First, that while the beautiful is concerned with form, the sublime may even be (or even especially be) formless. Second, that while the beautiful indicates (at least for judgment) a purposiveness of nature that may have profound implications, the sublime appears to be 'counter-purposive'. That is, the object appears ill-matched to, does 'violence' to, our faculties of sense and cognition. Robert Raikes Clewis, 2003, Aesthetic and moral judgment: The Kantian sublime in the "Observations", the "Remarks" (translated), and the "Critique of Judgment" (Immanuel Kant), Boston College, elaborated that in the earlier accounts (Part I), the four types of the sublime (das Erhabene )-the splendid, the noble, the terrifying, and the grotesque-share a bipolar structure of positive uplift and negative descent ; moral judgment is not clearly distinguished from aesthetic judgment. In the Observations, moral feeling is defined in terms of sublimity, and in both accounts moral judgment is involved in distinguishing apparent from genuine sublimity. However, four types of sublimity in the Critique of Judgment Part II, are characterized: the mathematical, the dynamical, the moral, and the sublime of mental states.
11.Theodore Gracyk, © 2002, 2004 PHILOSOPHY OF ART, HUME AND KANT: Summary and Comparison, http://www.mnstate.edu/gracyk/courses/phil of art/ hume_and_kant.htm#6, elaborated that although Kant's account of genius points towards nineteenth century Romanticism, sections 48 and 50 emphasize that genius produces great art only when reigned in by taste. Without an element of "academic correctness" constraining the artwork's form, genius risks nonsense. Yet rather than communicate according to established conventions, genius involves originality in which "nature gives the rule to art."

12 comments:

  1. Herlingga Putuwita Nanmumpuni
    18709251033
    S2 Pendidikan Matematika B 2018

    Estetika adalah ilmu yang membahas bagaimana keindahan bisa terbentuk, dan bagaimana supaya dapat merasakannya. Manusia pada umumnya menyukai sesuatu yang indah, baik terhadap keindahan alam maupun keindahan seni. Ketika menyaksikan dan merasakan keindahan dapat membuat perasan menjadi tenang dan bahagia. Dan sebenar-benar keindahan alam maupun seni haruslah senantiasa kita jaga dan lestarikan keberadaannya.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Seftika Anggraini
    18709251016
    S2 PM A 2018

    Menurut Kant, keindahan harus dipahami sebagai tujuan. Namun bukan tujuan tertentu akan mengarah ke keperluan eksternal atau keperluan internal. Beautiful judgment harus bersifat universal, tidak memihak. Indah itu berkaitan dengan rasa. Judgment dilakukan untuk menghasilkan kebahagiaan, bukan kebahagiaan yang menghasilkan judment. Hal ini juga berlaku untuk jedgment of beautiful.
    Terima kasih

    ReplyDelete
  3. Fabri Hidayatullah
    18709251028
    S2 Pendidikan Matematika B 2018

    Penilaian keindahan berkaitan dengan bagaimana cara menentukan sesuatu yang memiliki keindahan. Menurut Immanuel Kant, judgment adalah sebutan yang sederhana untuk kombinasi operasi pada kemampuan khusus. Ia berspekulasi bahwa operasi pada judgment dapat diorganisasikan dan diarahkan oleh prinsip a priori fundamental. Menurutnya, judgment menghubungkan antara pemahaman dan alasan. Pemahaman adalah kemampuan untuk membuat penilaian, sedangkan alasan ialah kemampuan untuk membuat penyimpulan. Kant kemudian membedakan antara keputusan dan judgment reflektif. Menurutnya, judgment keindahan merupakan bentuk yang menarik dari relfektif judgment. Judgment keindahan ialah sebuah filsafat keindahan yang menjelaskan kondisi-kondisi subjek dalam mengalami sesuatu yang indah, tidak hanya objek karya seni, tetapi terhadap objek secara umum.

    ReplyDelete
  4. Bayuk Nusantara Kr.J.T
    18701261006

    Objek dari suatu keputusan yang bersifat estetik adalah “bentuk” dari objek yang ditentukan dalam dirinya sendiri (considered in itself) (misalnya: komposisi warna dalam suatu pemandangan) dan diarahkan kepada subjek. Subyek kemudian menemukan kepuasan bagi dirinyaa. Untuk menyadari keindahan estetis, subjek (ego) haruslah terbebas dari sesautu yang sifatnya teoritis atau praktis. Keputusan estetik bukanlah pengetahuan sejati, namun hal tersebut merupakan kondisis subjek untuk mengekspresikan sesuatu yang indah.

    ReplyDelete
  5. Agnes Teresa Panjaitan
    S2 Pendidikan Matematika A 2018
    18709251013

    Pemahaman saya berdasarkan tulisan diatas adalah pendapat Kant mengenai estetika yang memenuhi beberapa jenis yaitu judgement(penilaian), pengalaman, konsep, properti, ataupun kata-kata. Burnham menyatakan bahwa estetika penilaian memiliki emoat bentuk berbeda yaitu ketidakberpihakan, universal, kebutuhan dan akhir tanpa akhir. Ketidakberpihakan disini dikarenakan penilaian yang sifatnya menyenangkan, universal dan kebutuhan dikarenakan karna hal tersebut adalah produk pikiran dan meliki tujuan tanpa tujuan atau akhir tanpa akhir karena penilaian tersebut memberi efek tanpa adanya tujuan.

    ReplyDelete
  6. Muh. Fachrullah Amal
    18709251036
    S2 Pendidikan Matematika B 2018

    Seperti yang kita ketahui bahwa estetika merupakan nilai yang berdasar atas keindahan. Menurut Kant bahwa estetika dapat terpenuhi apabila memuat macam hal seperti penilaian, pengalaman, konsep, sifat, atau kata-kata. Dunia ini memiliki estetika yang sangat banyak, kita dapat menemukannya berdasarkan penilaian atas apa yang kita temukan atau pandang. Estetika yang kita temukan bersifat objektif, sangat tergantung pada apa yang kita lihat. Kemudian Kant menambahkan bahwa penilaian itu mengahasilkan kesenangan bukan kesenangan menghasilkan penilaian.

    ReplyDelete
  7. Rindang Maaris Aadzaar
    18709251024
    S2 Pendidikan Matematika 2018 (PM B 2018)

    Assalamualaikum warahmatullahi wabarakatuh
    Elegi diatas menjelaskan tentang estetika. Terdapat pula jenis-jenis dari penilaian estetika, yaitu sifat estetik, pengalaman estetik, konsep estetik, dan kata-kata estetik. Penilaian estetik adalah berasal dari penilaian estetika. Pengalaman estetika adalah pengalaman yang mendasari penilaian estetika. Konsep estetika adalah konsep yang digunakan dalam penilaian estetika. Kata-kata estetika adalah kata-kata yang biasanya digunakan dalam ekspresi linguistik dari penilaian estetika.
    Wassalamualaikum warahmatullahi wabarakatuh

    ReplyDelete
  8. Dita Aldila Krisma
    18709251012
    PPs Pendidikan Matematika A 2018

    Menurut Kant, penilaian terhadap keindahan atau kecantikan ada 4 pertimbangan. Keempat pertimbangan itu adalah disinterested, universal, necessary, dan final without end. Disinterested berkaitan dengan selera dalam memberi keputusan senang atau tidak senang. Universal kaitannya dengan yang menyenangkan itu bersifat menyeluruh. Necesssary karena keindagan atau kecantikan merupakan produk dari fitur pemikiran manusia. Final without end maksdunya konsep yang dibuat bersifat purposive yakni memiliki tujuan atau harus mempengaruhi kita seolah-olah memiliki tujuan meskipun tidak ada tujuan khusus yang dapat ditemukan.

    ReplyDelete
  9. Fany Isti Bigo
    18709251020
    PPs UNY PM A 2018

    Berdasarkan tulisan ini makan Kant menjelaskan bahwa penilaian estetika (rasa) memiliki 4 kunci yaitu tidak memihak, universal, kebutuhn dan final tanpa akhir. Tidak memihak berkaitan dengan selera dalam memberi keputusan, universal berarti melibatkan harapan atau klaim atas persetujuan orang-orang.

    ReplyDelete
  10. Elsa Apriska
    18709251005
    S2 PM A 2018
    Menurut Kant bahwa penilaian estetika atau penilaianrasa harus memiliki empat kunci yang membedakan yakni tidak memihak, universal, kebutuhan dan final tanpa akhir. Penilaian bersifat tidak memihak artinya ketika kita menikmati sesuatu maka kita menilai itu indah, daripada menilai itu indah karena kita menganggapnya menyenangkan. Penilaian estetika bertindak secara universal yaitu melibatkan harapan atau klaim atas persetujuan orang lain.

    ReplyDelete
  11. Wilis Putri Hapsari
    19701251017
    S2 PEP A 2019

    An aesthetic judgment, in Kant's usage, is a judgment which is based on feeling, and in particular on the feeling of pleasure or displeasure. According to Kant's official view there are three kinds of aesthetic judgment: judgments of the agreeable, judgments of beauty (or, equivalently, judgments of taste. Thus aesthetic judgement by Kant now be a philosophical base for anyone who have desire to improve their knowledge on the transcendental theory and practice.

    ReplyDelete
  12. Syaiful Syamsuddin
    19701261002
    S3 PEP 2019
    Assalamu alaikum wr.wb
    Burnham, 2003, menurut Kant bahwa penilaian estetika atau penilaian rasa harus memiliki empat kunci yang membedakan fitur: tidak memihak, universal, kebutuhan dan final tanpa akhir. Estetika erat kaitannya dengan seni. Proses karya seni adalah sesuatu yang dibuat dengan penuh rasa dan dijiwai sehingga menghasilkan suatu karya yang tidak hanya indah untuk dipandang tetapi juga mempunyai makan yang tersimpan di baliknya. Dalam aesthetics judgment, Kant menggunakan istilah momen untuk merepresentasikan estetika atau keindahan. Setiap momen mempunyai tingkatan tersendiri tentang kualitas dan pertimbangan atas selera tentang keindahan

    ReplyDelete